Stanovich and colleagues recently developed a
prototype of the first comprehensive assessment of rational thinking. The test
is discussed, and presented in detail in the new book, titled- The Rationality Quotient.
Up until publication of- The Rationality Quotient - components of rational thinking had been
tested using various tasks, but a comprehensive test was not available. I first
discussed the development of such a test with Stanovich, in 2013- interview here.
In the following interview (conducted in November,
2016) Stanovich provides detailed answers to important questions about the
test.
What
are some of the initial reactions, regarding the RQ, from academics?
Uniformly positive so far, and I believe that is
because we were careful in the book to be explicit about two things. First, we were clear about what our goals
were and the goals were circumscribed.
Secondly, we included an entire chapter contextualizing our test (the Comprehensive
Assessment of Rational Thinking, CART) and discussing caveats regarding its use
as a research instrument or otherwise. In fact, I think we have already entirely achieved
our aims. We have a prototype test that
is a pretty comprehensive measure of the rational thinking construct and that
is grounded in extant work in cognitive science. Now, this is not to deny that there is still
much work to be done in turning the CART into a standardized instrument that
could be used for practical purposes.
But of course a finished test was not our goal in this book. Our goal was to show a demonstration of
concept, and we have done that. We have
definitively shown that a comprehensive test of rational thinking was possible
given existing work in cognitive science.
This is something that I have claimed in previous books but had not
empirically demonstrated with the comprehensiveness that we have here by
introducing the CART. As I said, there
are more steps left in turning the CART into an “in the box” standardized
measure, but that is a larger goal than we had for this book.
I think that, at least so far, most academics have
understood our goals and the feedback has been good. We wrote a summary article on the CART in a
2016 issue of the journal Educational
Psychologist (51, 23-34) and the
feedback from that community has been good.
Are
there components of the RQ that can be expected to show a strong positive correlation
with intelligence?
The CART has 20 subtests and four thinking
dispositions scales (the latter are not part of the total score). Collectively
they tap both instrumental rationality and epistemic rationality. In cognitive science, instrumental rationality
means behaving in the world so that you get exactly what you most want, given
the resources (physical and mental) available to you. Epistemic rationality concerns how well
beliefs map onto the actual structure of the world. The two types of rationality are
related. In order to take actions that
fulfill our goals, we need to base those actions on beliefs that are properly
calibrated to the world.
The CART assesses epistemic thinking errors such as:
the tendency to show incoherent probability assessments; the tendency toward
overconfidence in knowledge judgments; the tendency to ignore base rates; the
tendency not to seek falsification of hypotheses; the tendency to try to
explain chance events; the tendency to evaluate evidence with a myside bias;
and the tendency to ignore the alternative hypothesis.
Additionally, CART assesses instrumental thinking
errors such as: the inability to display
disjunctive reasoning in decision making; the tendency to show inconsistent
preferences because of framing effects; the tendency to substitute affect for
difficult evaluations; the tendency to over-weight short-term rewards at the
expense of long-term well-being; the tendency to have choices affected by vivid
stimuli; and the tendency for decisions to be affected by irrelevant
context.
Importantly, the test also taps what we call
contaminated mindware. This category of
thinking problem arises because suboptimal thinking is potentially caused by
two different types of mindware problems.
Missing mindware, or mindware gaps, reflect the most common type—where
Type 2 processing does not have access to adequately compiled declarative
knowledge from which to synthesize a normative response to use in the override
of Type 1 processing. However, in the
book, we discuss how not all mindware is helpful or useful in fostering
rationality. Indeed, the presence of
certain kinds of mindware is often precisely the problem. We coined the category label contaminated
mindware for the presence of declarative knowledge bases that foster irrational
rather than rational thinking. Four of
the 20 subtests assess contaminated mindware.
My purpose in digressing here to describe the CART
is to point out that given the number and complexity of rational thinking
skills, it is likely that the subtests will have correlations with intelligence
that are quite variable. The four
subtests with the highest correlations are: the Probabilistic Reasoning Subtest;
the Scientific Reasoning Subtest; the Reflection Versus Intuition Subtest; and
the Financial Literacy Subtest. Correlations
with these subtests tend to .50or higher. Most
of the subtests of the CART correlate with intelligence in the range of .25 to
.50 (a few have even lower correlations). Some very important components of
rational thinking do show considerable dissociation from intelligence. Overconfidence (measured by the Knowledge
Calibration Subtest of the CART) shows only a .38 correlation with
intelligence. This represents a
substantial amount of dissociation for a key component of rational
thinking. Kahneman, for example, devoted
substantial portions of his best-selling book to this component of rational
thinking. Myside bias (measured by our
Argument Evaluation Subtest) likewise shows a correlation of .38, indicating a
substantial dissociation. This thinking
bias is at the center of many discussions of what it means to be rational. Some of the subtests that most directly
measure the components of the axiomatic approach to utility maximization show
relatively mild correlations with intelligence.
For example, the Framing Subtest shows a fairly low .28
correlation. Framing measures a
foundational aspect of rational thinking according to the axiomatic approach.
Finally, some subtests of immense practical
importance show very low correlations with intelligence in the CART. The skill of assessing numerical expected
value shows a correlation of only .21, and the ability to delay for greater
monetary reward shows a correlation of only .06. The tendency to believe in conspiracies shows
a modest correlation of .34.
Do
you think rationality will acquire the same high level status as intelligence
in the near future?
Not in the near future, no. Our goal with the book was more modest—to
simply raise awareness of the importance of rational thinking and the ability
of modern cognitive psychology to measure it.
The result of our efforts will, we hope, redress the imbalance between
our tendency to value intelligence versus rationality. In our society, what gets measured gets
valued. Our aim in developing the CART
was to draw attention to the skills of rational thought by measuring them
systematically. In the book, we are
careful to point out that we operationalized the construct of rational thinking
without making reference to any other construct in psychology, most notably
intelligence. Thus, we are not trying to
make a better intelligence test. Nor are
we trying to make a test with incremental validity over and above IQ
tests. Instead, we are trying to show
how one would go about measuring rational thinking as a psychological construct
in its own right. We wish to accentuate
the importance of a domain of thinking that has been obscured because of the
prominence of intelligence tests and their proxies. It is long overdue that we had more
systematic ways of measuring these components of cognition, that are important
in their own right, but that are missing from IQ tests. Rational thinking has a unique history
grounded in philosophy and psychology, and several of its subcomponents are
firmly identified with well-studied paradigms.
The story we tell in the book is of how we have turned this literature
into the first comprehensive device for the assessment of rational thinking
(the CART).
Why
does society need a comprehensive assessment of rational thinking?